Friday, September 21, 2012

The Concept of Art Part 2.



Obviously talk about art could be a valuable interest adding exercise if the discourse was straight forward, easy to grasp and promoted a vocabulary that allowed us the ability to use what  we have gleaned from our previous experiences with art to extend our understanding.  The object is to provide shared experiences based on a point of reference that all would understand.  Aesthetics does not seem to offer us such a means.  As George Dickey points out “The attempt to discover a core for aesthetics is an attempt to provide stability and organization for what is by common agreement an untidy discipline.” Dickey, George, Aesthetics, Pegasus, Indianapolis, (1971) pp 109

Referring back to Carroll’s claim concerning statues that - “…it is immensely implausible to suppose that these works are designed with any intention to exhibit significant form.” – we can say without hesitation that their form is significant in that they share three aspects with all other art works though they have different constituent parts.  The medium of a statue may be bronze or nickel or it may be carved in wood or made from welded pieces of metal.   A cast statue would require a mold to be made from a likeness in wood, plaster, clay or wax which would be part of the manner of presentation.   Most often the subject matter of a statue will be clear if it is not an abstract piece.  By attending to form we are able to show how newer (and perhaps outlandish) art works maintain continuity with past artworks.  Those who are concerned that there should be consideration for how an artwork relates to its predecessors need only to recognize the form of the work.  The understanding of form as I have presented it in part 1 avoids the difficulties philosophers conjure up when discussing what they call first art and mid-life art.  Stephen Davies puts the argument this way:


First art should be distinguished from two things with which it could be confused: (a) it must be distinct from the progenitors from which it sprang.  The first art-making practices probably arose from others with which they were historically and culturally continuous, rather than appearing from thin air, but these other practices could not have been art-making ones, whatever similarities they shared with those generating first art. (b) First art should be distinguished from mid- life art.  Items that were not art when they were created might have art status conferred on them retrospectively.  That is, from the perspective of an art tradition established long after the creation of certain pieces, we might decide that those pieces merit art status and treat them accordingly. Stephen Davies, Philosophical Perspectives on Art, Oxford University Press, (2007) pp 69



We have to remember that Davies is an aesthetician.  Works that cannot be said to have aesthetic properties cannot be art, first or otherwise.  Scratch marks on a cave wall cannot be said to be primitive art. They are not art because they lack the form we identify as art.  (We will discuss this further in a later post.) Scratch marks on a cave wall would be one of the progenitors of first art that Davies speaks of.  But hand prints on a cave wall do, however, have form as art and while they may fail the aesthetician’s requirements in that they lack aesthetic properties they are unquestionably works of art.  The hand print has a medium (usually ochre using saliva as a binder).  It has a manner of presentation (blown from the mouth or tube over the hand onto a cave wall that enhances its appearance) and an obvious subject matter.  The hand print qualifies as first art.  A number of caves show a series of fist size dots in different colors and in rows which were either brushed or blown onto the ceilings. Because their medium and subject matter are indistinguishable they also fail to qualify as first art. 

It is clear from Davies’ argument that he sees mid-life art as something that has merit conferred upon it when he states “…we might decide that those pieces merit art status and treat them accordingly.’  What Davies is thinking about here is something like African Bakongo Nkisi Nail  fetish statues from the Congo (Figure 9.) whereby nails are driven into a carved wooden doll.  In some tribes they have been used to settle disputes and in others they are used to seek a spirit’s protection.  Several Art Museums have acquired these dolls displaying them as artworks though they were never intended as such.  Consequently Davies calls them mid-life art; objects that didn’t start out as art but became art once their aesthetic qualities were recognized. 

                                                    African Bakongo Nkisi Nail fetish statue. 


Actually, recognition is not an aesthetician’s preferred description. Rather, conferred as art is how many aestheticians promote the activity.  The reason being is that we cannot recognize mid-life art unless we have a concept that we apply to it.  But it seems we can look at an artifact and describe it in aesthetic terms thereby conferring art on it without being able to describe a concept of art.

As Davies’ concept of art involves meritorious accomplishment there can be no such thing as bad art.  If a work has no discernible aesthetic properties it cannot be called art.  Davies description of mid-life art demonstrates David Lewis-Williams’ claim that an aesthetic sense comes after the appearance of art which demonstrates the two uses of the term ‘art’.  For Davies the term art is evaluative (meritorious) whereas for Lewis-Williams it is classificatory (belonging to a class of objects regardless of merit).  What this means for Lewis-Williams is that a work of art need not have any aesthetic properties.  By the same token it is quite possible that a work will have meritorious (aesthetic) elements but lack integrity as a work of art though Davies may find such a situation disconcerting.   Unfortunately there are artists today that seek to create aesthetic works without consideration of form.  Fantasy art where subject matter and technique overwhelms medium and manner of presentation is a case in point.

Noël Carroll comes closest to an understanding of form when he discusses Artistic Form but his thesis is contaminated by his previous discussion of the neoformalist’s form/content argument. Carroll proposes: “Perhaps the most common way of thinking of artistic form is to conceive of it as one half of a distinction – the distinction between form and content.”(137)  He discusses the many items that may make up a painting and confronts a dilemma.  “The problem is that, at various times and in various contexts, any of these things or combinations thereof can be and have been identified as the content of such paintings.  But that renders the distinction between form and content unstable.” (138) As it has been shown, form is constituted by recognizing that it has three aspects that allow us to distinguish how the different parts of an art work contribute to the whole.  Carroll confuses form with shape and is stuck with a form/content dilemma and seems unable extract himself.

Wisely Carroll forgoes the attempt to describe artistic form by linking it with content.   Artistic form, he decides is composed of unified parts.  “Parts and relations then are the basic ingredients of artistic form.”(140)  Carroll is close but he doesn’t get a cigar.  He fails to understand that Artistic form is a factor in all art works.  He misses the forest for the trees.  Recognizing that he is unable to offer a definition of art that will provide us with a concept of art he asks: “If we were possessed of such a definition, why would it be so difficult to extract?”(266)   My view is that aesthetics gets in the way but Carroll has asked the necessary question.  Why would we wish to call a work ‘art’ in any sense of the term when an art form is absent?  No doubt such a question plagued the organizers of the New York art show in 1917 when they received a submission from Marcel Duchamp.  Duchamp purchased a urinal from a plumbing supply store titled it ‘Fountain’ and signed it R. Mutt and submitted it in the open sculpture section.

It caused uproar in the art world, was refused entry and mysteriously disappeared.  Duchamp subsequently remade the work for several galleries. Since, it has become clear that Fountain’ is not only a clear demonstration of its art form; it has proved to be the flag ship of a major movement in art. Of course there are still some scholars who insist that it should be placed in a subspecies of non-serious art such as Amusement Art.    

                                            Duchamp's Fountain (Copy 1964)     


There is a long joke that has circulated among artist concerning the painter Pablo Picasso.  It seems he was sought out by an admirer who had inherited an unsigned painting and the admirer’s deceased ancestor had insisted he had watched Picasso paint the work.  When the earnest admirer confronted Picasso with the painting to ensure its authenticity Picasso gave it a quick glance and declared it to be junk.  The admirer protested and informed Picasso that his deceased ancestor had actually watched him paint the work to which Picasso replied “I paint a lot of junk!”
 
The point of this abbreviated story is to bring to the fore the understanding that very accomplished artists make a lot of works that are not exemplary.  After all artists are not superhuman beings, they sometimes, unknowingly, make mistakes, misjudgments and careless works much the same as those of us who are not artists. Of course they do not have to display works they think are lacking.  But how are we to describe such works?  An equally probing question would be “Can a work be appreciated as an aesthetic piece and yet not be an exemplary work?”  Some aestheticians would offer a flat ‘no’ to the question.    If we accept the thesis that the perception of an aesthetic quality is the defining condition for a work of art, we are still left without an understanding of a concept of art.  We are obliged to accept the possibility that the perception of an aesthetic quality is not fundamental to describing a work as art.  This would mean that we could have works of art in which no aesthetic quality was perceived.  While aestheticians may well consider such a state of affairs tantamount to heresy the statement is, nevertheless, in some sense true. Some may wish to argue that a work that provides the opportunity for the creative act has by definition an aesthetic quality but then they would have to abandon a number of their aesthetic principles.

The concept ‘form’ has been in public usage for over two thousand years.  Plato is perhaps the first philosopher to establish the concept’s credentials.  Commonly, English writers translate Plato’s use of the term to mean ‘idea’ but the Greek sense of the word included how a thing looks.  In Latin documents we find the word ‘species’ substituting for the term ‘form’ and we extrapolate the term form to be ‘a kind of thing’.  This is surely what is meant when we use the term ‘art form’.  Our art forms are categories that contain things of a kind some of which are exemplary works while others are merely examples of the form. 

To be continued…


     
Launt Thompson 

http://www.amazon.com/s/ref=nb_sb_noss?field-keywords=Launt+Thompson&url=search-alias%3Daps&x=16&y=9

                                                                              













                                                             

No comments:

Post a Comment